domingo, 2 de febrero de 2025

OBEDIENCE AND COLLECTIVE CONSCIENCE: THEIR ROLES IN SOCIAL CHANGE AND EMPOWERMENT

 


ABSTRACT

This is an analytical essay in which I reflect on the theme of obedience and social consciousness. Studies in psychology, philosophy, and history that deal with these issues often limit their reviews to interpretations consonant with their own clearly delineated disciplines. The overriding objective of this paper is to explore these topics from a varied theoretical approach, and to find commonalities in them. These concepts have a number of nuances, reflecting distinct and even opposing psychological, cultural and philosophical dimensions. In its basic definition “obedience” refers to a situation in which a person accepts the instructions or orders of another individual or group. Their obedience may be voluntary or involuntary. In the latter case obedience becomes submission. The idea of “consciousness” can refer to personal or socially shared awareness, and in many cases, it is the antithesis of obedience.

Key words: individual consciousness, collective consciousness, obedience, active minorities, cognitive dissonance  


INTRODUCTION

Groups and individuals that offer assistance and interventions in communities and vulnerable neighborhoods often limit their appreciation of empowerment to certain specific goals that, once achieved, lead to the participants’ increased sense of personal capacitation. This may or may not include a critical social- and self-awareness. As Fabricio Balcazar, Christopher. Keys, and Julie Vryhof (2019) point out, this helps individuals in identifying personal and contextual factors that are related to their groups’ achievements, their own attainment of new skills, and access to financial capital and to other resources and opportunities. The authors observe that by increasing the participants’ skills and access to resources they may increase their sense of psychological enfranchisement.

Real personal empowerment and social change require, however a deeper appreciation of the social determinants that affect them. The overriding objective of this paper is to explore ideas about obedience and social consciousness in ways that include their development in social psychology, history, and philosophy. When people become aware of the multiple ways in which different forms of obedience affect their lives, whole new worlds are open to them.

The word “obedience” has psychological, philosophical, legal, and historical connotations, but in its basic meaning, it refers to a situation in which a person accepts the instructions or orders of another individual or group.  In some cases, this compliance is voluntary, but in others it is forced, as in the case of submission or subjection. Obeying can also refer to a reasoned assent to the influence of others. It can likewise be considered as compliance with a set of principles or moral dictates. Social consciousness is normally the antithesis of obedience, but when it refers to obeying the dictates of reasoned reflection, both experiences may form part of the same phenomenon.

Obviously, part of the problem is semantical. Obedience may mean: a) submission to another person’s wishes or orders, b) the acceptance of a creed or a faith as in monastic obedience, c) the acceptance of reasoned principles as in the practice of scientific research (the adoption of the principles of systematic skepticism, objectivity, reliability and accountability), d) the acceptance of generally acknowledged secular laws, and e) the disciplined acceptance of the dictates of one’s conscience.  In the same way consciousness has many meanings; it may mean a simple awareness, as in being awake, or a deeper personal awareness as in the perception of one’s own emotional states. It can also refer social consciousness that happens when people collectively elaborate aspects of their social world.

Obeying is an act that may be active, or not (like the contrast between raising one's hand to vote -an act-, and standing motionless at a red light -inaction-); it can imply the observance of rule, a custom, or an order, sometimes without reflecting on the goodness or convenience of this compliance.  Accepting a suggestion or indication after assessing the potential benefits – or the ethics of agreeing to its fulfilment – is also part of its cluster of meanings.

There are two main problems to overcome when reflecting on the noun "obedience." First, as I have noted, it is a word with an enormous variety of meanings, some of which are contradictory. Second, the different meanings of this word may have incompatible contexts, and even lexicons. We can briefly mention three examples of these contexts. Firstly, a thesis student may accept or reject his or her tutor’s suggestions. In this case the student does not have to obey even though the tutor is obviously an authority. Rather, he or she must reason his decision. In another case, children may reason with a parent or a teacher after receiving a command, even though they know that they will finally have to accept the what the authority figure decides. But in another context a soldier or a police officer may find it more difficult to refuse an order from his superior.  All of these examples have social and ethical relevance for us. It is a subject with important cultural roots and affective impact, and its ambiguity increases its social force. It is necessary to examine these discrepancies and compare them. We all obey. Children are expected to respect the warnings of their parents and teachers. At the social level in democracies, laws are supposed to be the product of a collectively established social pact. It is assumed that they represent the will of the population they impact, and therefore they must be respected by all citizens.

In this article I consider – from very different points of view – the general concept of obedience. The reason for this diversity is the need to encompass the concept in its breadth. Since the Nuremberg Trials, which we consider in this text, obedience has been a collective, political, and personal problem. It is closely related to other concepts such as legal and ethical responsibility, which in a liberal democracy falls on the individual and not on groups or families as was the case in Roman and medieval law.

In this work, I define the notion as: action of complying a) with the will of another person or group, b) with a cultural norm or a law, c) with a social obligation, or d) with a majority. I include in these reflections the effects of operant conditioning as in studies on behavioral modification with respect to learning of contingencies.   

The organization of this article is as follows: First, I make a brief reference to:  certain works in social and behavioral psychology. Then I discuss certain historical and legendary references (such as Iphigenia's obedience to her father Agamemnon, and Abraham's obedience to God). I end this section with a consideration of the notion of due obedience for state officials and military personnel, and a reflection on the position of the Nuremberg trials. 

In the end I consider the capacity we have to say "no" as elaborated by Mead, Sartre and Schütz. I conclude with some final reflections.

 

METHOD

I have employed the structure of the essay in these reflections. They consist of a general consideration of the ideas of obedience and consciousness, which are topics of urgent interest to all the social sciences. I have written this from a personal perspective, largely according to my own experiences with community facilitation projects. I have intentionally chosen diverse areas of thought (psychological research, interpretation of legends, considerations on legal provisions regarding military practices and reflections on certain philosophical positions related to the existential capacity we have to choose). These themes touch the breadth of human experience, and demonstrate the complexity of the thinking subject. There is much content that I have had to ignore, or mention only very briefly; my criterion for selecting these topics – in the short space of this article – was the need to cover the concept broadly enough to be able to include the main trends for psychologists, sociologists, historians, philosophers, and other professions.

Due to the personal nature of these reflections, I have used the grammatical first person to express my positions. I consider this to be an ethical position, that is, that of taking responsibility for the text.

Justification

Obedience is a topic that has preoccupied social psychologists for more than seventy years. With different methodological approaches, Milgram (1963 and 2005), Zimbardo (2009), Asch (1956), and Moscovici (1996) have considered its social and ethical aspects, along with the disturbing implications of conformity and deference to the majority, in the sense of the submission of the individual to the dictates of a collectivity.

The same uneasiness appears in very old contexts of reflection. Beginning with the Old Testament and the Greek tragedies of the sixth century B.C., we find similar doubts. I have felt it necessary to include these legends because obeying has had a very positive cultural value for a long time and, at the same time, its ethical price has been repeatedly questioned. We are the inheritors of these contradictory traditions. Complying with the king's demands was an obligation that was almost never put in doubt. But from the beginning of historical times there have been certain authors such as the Greeks Sophocles and Euripides, and later the Renaissance and the Enlightenment thinkers, such as Erasmus, Shakespeare, Michel de Montaigne, Rousseau and Voltaire that opened the door to dissidence. Some of them paid a heavy price for their nonconformity, for example, Giordano Bruno.

The thinking that has been done about obedience is quite varied. On the one hand, in the XVII century there was Thomas Hobbes (n.d.) for whom submission formed the philosophical basis of an ideal society. Hobbes's work is a justification of the absolute state. He proposed the idea of a social contract that he considered necessary because, in his opinion, people are essentially selfish. For this reason, he felt that they have to submit to a greater power in order to live in peace. Hobbes considered that the only way people have to defend themselves against the invasion of foreigners and against the wrongs of others is to give all the state’s power to one man or an assembly of men. The citizens can vote to authorize “one will” to act in everyone’s name. Hobbes considered this kind of renouncement to be an act of “unity”. This done, the multitude, thus united in one person called state, leads to the generation of the Leviathan, or the supreme good personalized in one leader (Hobbes,  p. 99-100).

On the other hand, from ancient times, there have been severe criticisms of the virtues of political obedience. For example, in the fifth century before the Cristian era, Sophocles (Antigone full text.pdf. n.d.) wrote the play Antigone. In this play the main character refuses to obey Creon, the king. Antigone says that she can say “no” to anything she considers “vile”. Creon sentences her to death for this. The play, far from being an account of justice achieved, is a tragedy in which Creon himself pays a severe price for his heavy-handedness.

In the European Renaissance, Étienne de la Boétie in 1572, at the beginning of his book, "Discourse on Voluntary Servitude" (2015), expressed his reasons for writing it as follows. He said that he wanted to find out how so many men, so many cities, and so many nations submit to the yoke of a single tyrant. A king really has no more power than what his subjects give him, and he can only harm them if they comply with his demands. (p. 18).

Obedience is not always unwanted. As I have pointed out, it is appropriate to obey the law in a democracy. The referee is obeyed in competitive games. It refers to something complex in human culture that must be seen in its multiplicity.

THE MULTIPLICITY OF MEANINGS FOR “OBEDIENCE”

Social psychology and behaviorism

Two of the particular research areas in which obedience has been a subject of study is in social psychology and behaviorism. They have their own methods and vocabularies, and they stand out for presenting particular theoretical positions on people’s tendency to obey. In this context they obey the expectations of authority or the expectations of the majority. In behavioral (operant conditioning) terms they learn (obey) the contingencies in their environment and act accordingly. In what follows I review the studies of Milgram (1963 and 2005), Zimbardo (Stanford Prison Experiment, and 2007), Asch (1956), Moscovici (1996) and Skinner (1985).

Milgram’s experiments

Milgram (2005) showed that people tend to obey certain figures recognized as legitimate authorities. In a widely known work, he employed an experimental situation in which participants were ordered to perform acts which probably contradicted their own norms, that is, they were ordered to harmfully punish a third person. In reality, the experiment was a feigned situation in which no one was really hurt. The orders were given by a simulated "experimenter" dressed in a lab jacket, and the setting was a replication of a psychological experimental lab. The subjects believed they were participating in a scientific study of operant learning, and they did not know the real reason for their contribution.  The study was replicated by Jerry Burger (2009) with slight changes. He obtained obedience rates that were similar to Milgram’s, who found that most of the subjects obeyed the orders they received, without questioning the ethics of their actions. In this case the experiment deals with blind obedience to an authority figure.

Zimbardo's experiments

A study conducted by Zimbardo (2007) at Stanford University is also well known. Zimbardo simulated a prison situation and assigned the subjects to different groups: the prison “authorities”, the "prisoners" and the "guards." In the results, the participants assigned as imprisoned inmates recreated the situation of obedience to their jailers, and the guards, and on their own initiative, took the role of repressors, sometimes in a brutal way, as if it were a real prison. Any one of the subjects could have ended their participation at any time. All participants took on roles known to them, without reflecting on why they were doing so.

Zimbardo said in his book, The Lucifer Effect (2007), that one of the main conclusions of the Stanford prison experiment is that the subtle power of situational variables can override the will to resist this influence. The participants in these studies were ordinary college students or volunteers. They had had no experience with prisons, and yet they ended up obeying an assumed social norm to the point of cruelty. They did things they never would have imagined they would do.

Zimbardo examined a number of psychological processes that can induce a good person “to do wrong”, including de-individuation, obedience to authority, passivity in the face of threats, self-justification, and rationalization. Another fundamental psychological process is dehumanization. It describes attitudes that do not allow people to see others as human beings. It turns them into enemies who “deserve” torment, torture, and even extermination (Zimbardo, 2007, Prologue, p. 6).

What is the main difference between obedience as described by Milgram and Zimbardo? In the case of the former, the participants obey an authority figure, even against their own normative systems. In the second case, they assumed without question a system of social roles widely known in their culture.  This second type of obedience is not induced by an authority figure, at least not directly. It is situational, where cultural aspects, social expectations, social pressure, and self-justification interact to shape the behavior of individuals. These situations appear naturally in total institutions such as prisons, in the military world, and even in schools where the social expectations of closed groups lead to phenomena such as bullying.

 Asch and Mosovici

In the two cases reviewed so far, the experimenters simulated situations in which obedience is expected, that is, the subjects assume roles where there are culturally regulated behaviors (obedience to an authority or to a system of known roles).

In the case of Solomon Asch (1956) the situation is different: the authority is "a majority", that is, an abstract entity.  In an experiment he carried out, the participants were expected to make correct judgments about the length of a clearly defined set of lines that were presented to a group in which they formed a part. They were told that it was an study dealing with perception. The experimental participant was always one of the last to speak. All the others in the group were collaborators in the experiment, and all gave identical but incorrect answers. When it was the turn for the experimental subjects to give their answers, they found themselves alone, a minority of one. In this situation they tended to bow to the artificial collectivity, and would join the majority in their answers. This was interpreted as the power of the majority over the minority.

Later, Serge Moscovici, in The Psychology of Active Minorities (1996) reported on modifications he made in the experiments carried out years earlier by Asch. He repeated the original format, but added one more accomplice, whose task was to give the correct answer before the subject's turn. With this backing, the experimental subjects dared to follow their own inclinations and responded with the correct answer.

Moscovici, referring to this phenomenon in real-life situations, called the dissidents who first dare to say the truth, "deviants from the majority" or "active minorities." His book recognizes examples of these minorities in political life, including the history of the Russian dissident Aleksandr Isayevich Solzhenitsyn, Nobel laureate and Russian author of several books, including A Day in the Life of Ivan Denisovich. In this book Solzhenitsyn denounced abuses committed in Stalin’s Russia. His book acted as a breach in the political dam of that country, and provoked a debate about the negative aspects of Stalinism among people who previously had perceived these wrongs, but who had not dared to express an opinion.

As Moscovici (1996) points out, an individual’s behavior ensures his or her membership in the social environment. Reality is considered as something uniform, and deviation from the norm represents a kind of failure in social insertion. Conformity is understood as consensus and balance.

For a long time, deviants have been treated as nuisances. Moscovici, on the other hand, re-labeled them as "active minorities" where they lose their pathological connotations in the face of dominant social expectations. They are individuals who have their own code of ethics, and today we recognize them among feminists, fighters for racial equity, "gays," and certain political opponents. Influenced by the example of the active minority, other people, who were previously marked by anomie, can engender their own place in society.

Operant conditioning

Operant conditioning does not refer directly to obedience as I have been defining it. Rather, it is a body of techniques for manipulating the environmental consequences of behavior. The positive reinforcement (reward) for a given behavior tends to increase its frequency, and negative reinforcement (punishment) tends to diminish it. A subject is more likely to repeat behaviors that are associated with positive consequences, and less likely to repeat those that produce negative results. In general, it is associative learning; behavioral contingencies can come "naturally" from the environment in an unmanipulated way, that is, in a "normal" way (for example, people take care where they step because of their experience with tripping), but they can also come from programs to artificially cause certain consequences. In this case, "obedience" is not necessarily conscious; the subject simply learns the contingencies of his acts.

Operant conditioning originated with the work of the psychologist Burrhus Frederic Skinner. Research that he and others have done has produced a very detailed technology that is used in teaching, medicine, psychology, and other disciplines, called "behavioral modification”.

There is an interesting account about its power in Skinner's autobiography A Matter of Consequences, (1985) in which he narrates an encounter with the humanist Erich Fromm. In 1958, the two attended a symposium. Fromm said that conditioning techniques do not take into account human free will, and told Skinner: "People are not pigeons" in reference to studies done by Skinner with this species. Skinner took revenge by making up a small conditioning session right there in relation to Fromm himself. He passed a small note to his friend Halleck Hoffman saying that he was going to condition Fromm's left hand. Fromm was sitting directly across the table from Skinner. Skinner turned his chair so that he could easily control the times in which he looked directly at Fromm who was gesticulating as he spoke. Then Skinner “rewarded” Fromm by looking at him directly when he raised his left hand. In a very short time, Fromm was moving his arm in the air so vigorously that his watch fell off. (Skinner, 1985 and Psyciencia, 2015).

In this story Fromm "obeyed" Skinner, but without knowing it. If Fromm had understood what Skinner was doing to him, he could have refused his involvement. Conditioning techniques work in two basic situations: a) when the subject is unaware of the disposition of contingencies, and b) when he is or she aware of them and accepts them. In fact, in certain addiction treatments, patients voluntarily undergo aversive conditioning programs to eliminate their unwanted habits.

Legends and institutions

In what follows we radically change our cultural references. The results of academic studies related to obedience are fundamentally different from the discourses on legends. The former point to the cognitive and emotional factors involved in the phenomenon. Legends, on the other hand, relate certain experiences that remain as stories or prototypes of behaviors that successive generations later judge, emulate or reject. They have different lexicons and contexts, and not all of them have survived culturally. The situations they describe are part of our theme, and because of their deep ancestral roots they cannot be ignored as if they were unrelated to modern experience. They are still relevant today, and they refer to very actual phenomena.

In a similar vein, I will review obedience in the military world. This context can be distinguished from all others. Obedience is the most fundamental duty of the soldier, but the 20th century has taught us that it must have limits, that when the order is illegal or immoral the soldier must obey a higher rule and disobey his chain of command.

Agamemnon

Greek mythology exalts the values of heroism, but also is concerned with the notion of destiny that sometimes haunts and bends heroes and kings, taking away the very qualities that could have made them great. In the following paragraph I will make a very brief synopsis of the Greek legend of Agamemnon’s family tragedy, and then analyze some aspects of his life in greater detail.

According to Euripides' play, "Iphigenia in Aulis" (Euripides, n.d.), the Greek queen Helen has run off with the Trojan prince, Paris; she was the wife of Menelaus, Agamemnon's brother. As the play opens, Agamemnon has been chosen as head of the army that will go to Troy to rescue her. When Agamemnon wanted to set sail with his soldiers however, he found himself stranded on the beaches due to bad weather, with multiple armies camped there and frustrated by the lack of deployment. An oracle told him that, in order to go to war, he had to sacrifice his daughter Iphigenia. She finally obeyed him, because she valued her filial duty more than she did her own life. Clytemnestra, the girl's mother, and Agamemnon's wife, also submitted to the oracle's will, but she never forgave her husband. It is a chronicle of bitterness and terror that begins with an ambitious hero who sacrifices everything for his own quest for glory and power: his legacy is hatred.

There are elements here that catch our attention: war has its demands. Once the powerful have assembled an army ready to go into battle, they have to fight or lose control of the situation. Power requires everyone’s obedience to its dynamics, even that of the rulers, and they become the artifacts of the mechanics of their own command. Agamemnon did not want to sacrifice his daughter, but he could no longer act according to his own will and at the same time maintain his kingdom.

The priest also knew the price of authority and command. He clearly didn’t have as much to lose as the king, but he knew that the soldiers, despite their tears over the impending immolation of the king's daughter, needed a sign from the monarch of his willingness to move on. Iphigenia herself obeyed: she meekly offered herself to the exactions of her rank: noblesse oblige. Blood requires more blood in this imaginary: the blood of the soldiers must be preceded by that of the royal house.

Agamemnon represents obedience to a culture that demands violence. He is not the only leader who has allowed himself to transgress the most basic norms of humanity: Greek tragedies and those of Shakespeare are full of these stories; in our time, the twentieth and twenty-first centuries also offer many non-fictional examples. In this short article there is no space to expand on the subject, but in the book "The Hero's Grip" (Cronick, 2018) this topic is developed more extensively.

Abraham

Another historical and legendary reference to obedience has to do with religious authority and not power strategies. It is a topic of interest now because there are acts of violence in the name of almost all faiths; certain individuals feel called upon to defend their dogmas with bombs, massacres, and guns.

The case of Abraham in the Old Testament[1] (recognized by the three major monotheistic religions) is of interest in our reflections. It is one of the first stories about violence as a direct command from God[2], but at the same time it contains the theme of forgiveness. Evidently in this sacred book there are countless stories in which God participates violently on behalf of the Israelites (the sacrifice of the Egyptian firstborn, the violence of Joshua in Jericho, and many other examples).   Abraham's willingness to sacrifice his son Isaac is an intimate account. It examines the father's motives and the son's obedience, and in many ways resembles Iphigenia’s obedience before Agamemnon leaves for Troy, although for Abraham it is an immensely painful duty. We find, however, a repeated theme here in very different cultural and historical sources. For this reason, they deserve our attention.[3]  Abraham’s story differs from that of Agamemnon because Abraham was not attempting to consolidate his power. His sacrifice was a pure case of religious obedience. 

Abraham, a wealthy Israeli patriarch from prehistoric times, appears in the Old Testament as Noah's heir. The sequence of events is:[4] God tested Abraham saying that he must take his only son, Isaac, to Moriah, and offer him as a burnt offering. Abraham obeyed, and erected an altar, laid out the wood, bound his son Isaac, and laid him on the altar on top of the wood. Then he took up a knife with the intention of killing him. But the Angel of the Lord called him from heaven saying not to do it. Once Abraham had shown obedience, it was not necessary to actually carry out the sacrifice.

The story has many possible interpretations, but in the context of this article we will concentrate on Abraham's direct obedience, and Isaac’s acceptance both of his father’s intentions and God’s will.

Kierkegaard (1954), using the pseudonym Johannes de Silentio, raises the image of Abraham's "dread" when he decides to obey God's order to sacrifice Isaac, the son of his old age who could have fulfilled the prophecy of being the progenitor of the Nation of Israel. Kierkegaard asks about the everyday morality of Abraham's obedience. He remembers that Abraham did not ask God to change his mind. Abraham acted out of faith that accepted God's command, as he also accepted (at the last moment) divine forgiveness for his son.

By placing Abraham in the category of the particular, Kierkegaard also places him in relation to Hegel: Abraham relates to God as does the Hegelian slave to the master in the Phenomenology of Spirit (Hegel, 1987). He does not obey separate consciousnesses, but an unhappy and global consciousness. Abraham cannot ask whether the divine command is right or true; he cannot ask whether the voice he heard really represented God's will: objective truth is not a valid goal to lessen the demands of such a jealous God.

Abraham is a loving and immensely pained father, but his experience can be related to other religious mandates – more nefarious – to kill in the name of a faith or an ideological or nationalist cause.

Due obedience and the modern state

In the military tradition we find another cultural lexicon and other historical contexts. The problem of due obedience for State officials, particularly among the military and police forces, remains unresolved. This modern problem can be distinguished from the obligation to obey the oracle experienced by Agamemnon and Iphigenia, or Abraham's obligation to accept God's will. It is not an obligation that requires sacrificial blood as a sign of obedience and submission to the tribe and culture. But it is related to a very long tradition of the relationship between kings, their generals, and their soldiers.

The military institution is an instance of the state characterized by an unbreakable chain of command; The soldier’s discipline rests on his immediate and unquestioned compliance with the orders of his superiors. In the military tradition, the man of arms cannot take the initiative to question the orders he receives from his superiors: he must answer "Yes, Sir!" and obey them. However, some demands may be illegal or immoral. What is the responsibility of the military subordinate in these cases?

National and international jurisprudence has not completely clarified the nature of these conditions; Since 1945, governments and world courts have debated two conflicting positions: a) the traditional expectations of due obedience in the military world, and b) the legal limits of military and civilian ethics.

It is worth reviewing these realities. In Spanish America, there are certain "exonerating" conditions from criminal responsibility for subordinates who "only follow orders." Here, I am using two Chilean authors Rocío Rivero Velarde (2016), and Juan Pablo Cavada (2019). According to the first, in the case of unlawful orders, Article 62 of Chilean Law No. 18,834, on the Administrative Statute states that:

... [it] contemplates the duty to represent an order that the official considers illegal before the superior, and in the event of the latter repeating it, the rule assumes that the official ... he must comply with it, being exempt from all responsibility, which will fall entirely on the superior who has insisted on the order.... (Rivero, 2016, p. 4)

In other words, according to this law, it is sufficient for the superior to repeat the illegal order for the official to have to comply with it. It is also understood that said official will be exempt from any personal responsibility.

Cavada, reviewing the penal codes of several Latin American countries (Bolivia, Colombia, Costa Rica, El Salvador and Nicaragua) and Spain, found similar "exonerating" situations. For example, Article 40 of the Bolivian Penal Code identifies the following mitigating circumstances for the responsibility of subordinates. The subordinate is exonerated:

When the perpetrator has acted for an honorable motive, or driven by misery, or under the influence of serious and unjust moral suffering, or under the impression of a serious threat, or by the ascendancy of a person to whom he owes obedience or on whom he depends (Cavada, p. 4).

On the other hand, Article 32 of the Colombian Penal Code adds: "Due obedience may not be recognized when it comes to crimes of genocide, forced disappearance and torture" (Cavada, p. 4).

In the United States soldiers may disobey an “unlawful” order, but it is not always possible to tell the difference between what is lawful and unlawful. Decisions about this tend to be “after the fact” in court cases. During the Vietnam War in the My Lai massacre, some of the officials were court-martialed for following orders to kill hundreds of civilians. The soldiers who refused to obey did not face court-martial. The court described the order as “palpably illegal” because the summary killing of an enemy who has submitted is murder. (Conorman and Dualan Attorneys at Law, 2022)

The need to make explicit the "exonerating" conditions in the penal codes of many countries is a direct reflection of three institutional instances: a) the Nuremberg trials, b) the International Court of Justice in The Hague originally established in 1945 and c) the subsequent approval of the Statute of Rome in 1998, all of which limit military immunity at the international level. Historically, before the adoption of these legal instruments, people – as individuals – were not responsible for having obeyed improper orders. The development of the individual’s legal responsibility occurred in the twentieth century; previously, legal and ethical obligations were limited to states, monarchies, and nations, as abstract entities.

The Nuremberg trials

The Nuremberg trials took place from November 1945 to October 1946 in accordance with the resolutions adopted by the United States of America, the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics, and Great Britain.

This trial established precedents and certain jurisprudence on the legal and moral responsibility of subordinate at the international level. The individual responsibilities of high-ranking members of Adolf Hitler's National Socialist regime were determined in relation to crimes and abuses against humanity committed in the name of the Third Reich. Hitler had already committed suicide. Among those sentenced were: Martin Borman, Karl Dönitz, Hans Frank, Wilhelm Frick, Hermann Göring, Rudolf Hess, Gustav Krupp and Joachim von Ribbentrop. The charges included: conspiracy against world peace, planning, provoking and conducting an offensive war, crimes and attacks against the Law of War, and inhuman crimes (EcuRed, n.d.).

The jurisprudence on crimes and abuses represented a legal advance that would later be reflected in the United Nations and also, from 1998 in the establishment of the Permanent International Criminal Court. The traditional approach to international law based on relations between States was also changed. At Nuremberg the idea of the rights and duties of private persons was added. Since then, crimes committed by people such as state officials could be tried internationally.

There was criticism of these trials for several reasons, including: (a) the judges tried "crimes" that had not been declared as such until after they had been committed (in violation of the guarantees of non-retroactive application of the law), (b) the judges came from the winning side in a war and those who were tried were the vanquished, and (c) among the "judges" was the Soviet Union, which had perpetrated similar crimes. However, given the enormity of the atrocities committed by National Socialism, it was evident that more than just a peace treaty was needed. Those subjected to trail had the right to legal representation and an individual trial in front of a judge.

From the second half of the twentieth century, it is assumed that there is in each individual the ability to deny the orders he receives from a superior.

The ability to say "no"

We have reviewed lexicons and cultural aspects that describe conflicting facets of obedience. We will now explore some existential and cultural stances that may be used to confront undue obedience.  First we will  review the possibility of consciousness as an corrective to undue obedience as elaborated by G.H. Mead (1972). He says that the personality “appears” in the form of multiple models that arise in the individual’s consciousness in appropriate contexts. Mead says that the self-aware human individual assumes the organized attitudes of his social group or community to which he belongs. This, of course, would include obligations with long cultural traditions, with what would be considered today ethically dubious elements.

But Mead says that the person is not completely subject to the norms of society; he can challenge them (say "no") using his inner voices.  According to Mead, the person is structurally divided into the "I" and the "me."[5] The "I" may react to the inner voices that arise from the “me”, thanks to the adoption of the attitudes of others.

The action of the "I" is spontaneous and does not reflect on anything. It is not perceptible within itself; This happens because the "I" exists only in the present. This actuality of the "I" is the mechanism that allows it to act with a certain independence of the "me." In Mead, the "I" does not react to the attitudes of others, but the "me" contains their viewpoints, as a series of organized outlooks that one adopts for oneself. 

It can even be said that the performance of the "I" is uncertain and unpredictable. Intuitively we can understand this by remembering occasions in which we have planned to act in a certain way, but when the moment arrives, we do something else. On a simple level we may plan to spend the afternoon working, but we end up loafing away the available time.

Although the "me" may demand a certain kind of "I", in the sense of fulfilling the expectations of itself that the former has developed, the "I" acts with palpable independence in the sense of the creation of new experience. It is through the autonomy between the parts of the psyche that spaces are opened for change, although we can then be surprised or even frightened when we reflect on our actions. In this way, we may have planned to say nothing about how we feel about a given issue at a coming meeting, but suddenly we find ourselves participating fully in all the discussions. Our “I” has liberated us to act.

There have been other formulations on this relationship between the immediate and the reflected. We can mention those of Schütz (1993) and Sartre (1989) which are very similar.  Sartre (1989) said that immediate and present consciousness has a past, but one cannot identify with it. This is so because one lives in the present: the person is radically free to determine (choose) what he or she is going to be (and do), and is absolutely responsible for these choices. We cannot even be aware of the immediate motives that impel us to act, because when we know them, they already exist in the past. In Sartre's famous phrase, we appreciate that: "I am condemned forever to exist beyond my essence, beyond the motives of my act: I am condemned to be free" (1989, p. 466). Sartre says that it is one of the most basic attributes of ontology, including our "for-itself",[6] that is, the flow of our past experience seen from the present; it is the only key we have to identify ourselves as subjects, but it has little to do with what we are or what we will be. It is only in the negation of the Hegelian "in-itself"[7] – what we are in the perpetual instant of now – that our identity can be elaborated. 

But, if Schütz and Sartre claim that we cannot control the next instant in our lives, they both recognize that the project of the person we have elaborated leads us in generally foreseen directions. That is, the project exists as a pattern from the past that influences us to a certain degree in our leap to the future that we experience at every moment of the present. It is only a project and not a mandate. For this reason, we are unpredictable: that jump to freedom is the great moment to initiate changes, and yet we may not take that opportunity.

It can also happen that people become so emotionally tied to their beliefs that they have difficulty challenging them (Festinger, 1968). In his book, A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance, Leon Festinger (1968) discussed how some people need to maintain a high level of uniformity in their beliefs. Underlying this tendency is a great deal of emotional insecurity, and fear of challenge. When these beliefs are false or inadequate, people use a variety of strategies to protect themselves from the truth. Extreme examples are beliefs that the Earth is flat or that vaccines cause cancer, but, in general, when people have a deep affective investment in particular views, it is hard for them to dispute them. This experience is called “cognitive dissonance”. It can cause anxiety, and this discomfort can increase one’s efforts to deny inconsistent -albeit correct- information. There are few “cures” for this situation. When the need to believe is weak, it is easier to overcome, but when it is strong people will go to great lengths to avoid the truth. Sometimes group pressure can weaken the need for consistency, but only when the group does not share the mistaken views. When the person’s social environment supports these views, change is difficult. Sometimes new information can overwhelm the old beliefs, but in general, the only way to productively deal with this conflict is through an increase in the person’s self-confidence and general emotional strength. This is not a situation of obedience to external entities; rather it is a case of obedience to one’s own past, and one’s self-image.

In a practical sense we can ask, what are the collective mechanisms for awakening a social consciousness? Some are clear: when we know the “real” rules we are obeying we can take a stance.  If someone had told the subjects in Asch’s, Milgram’s and Zimbardo's experiments that their ability to resist manipulation was being tested, they might have changed their behavior. If there were credible sources for interpreting the declarations made by public and state celebrities, people would not have to believe everything they hear. Mosovici has told us that one important tool of resistance is found in the social environment, especially in the presence of an active minority that relieves the pressure towards conformity and allows the individual to express his ideas more independently.

Another tool for reducing obedience is to teach and promote empathy. Cronick (2024) mentions how this capacity relates to people’s sense of identification. It has to do with individual and group affectivity, and relates also to massive political events. It is difficult for a pilot to drop bombs on a population when he or she has empathetic ties with those people.

Perhaps the most powerful tool for resisting thoughtless obedience is cultural and educational preparation. In an institutional sense, an accessible, comprehensive, and obligatory educational project for the entire population would be a basic, indispensable resource. A friend once told me how amazed she was when she first saw the periodic table on a classroom wall: she suddenly discovered that there is order in the universe, and that there are objective means for understanding it. It changed how she viewed her life from that moment on.[8] In other words, she added a new incentive to her accumulation of cultural wisdom.

The ability to say "no" is our primary tool against undue obedience. In it we have the possibility of a relative autonomy and can reflect on ourselves; we can deny our own intentions and those that the Other has in relation to us. We can even distance ourselves from our own life project as it has been in the past.

Of course, tyrants have resources, too, the chief of which is fear. There are times when we have said “no” in our inner dialogue, but are afraid to act or speak out.

A few additional brief thoughts on fundamentalism and obedience

In an article published 27 years ago, Carlos Kohn (1992) reflected on the nature of fundamentalism, which he defined as:

… any subordination of concrete men, that is, as individuals, to an abstract principle radically superior to themselves, which legitimizes a given or proposed social order, as an all-encompassing prescription of the "ought to be" [and recreates the] Behemont […] under the tutelage of a Leviathan (The State) to use Hobbesian language (Kohn, p. 74).

This is an allusion to Hobbes second book in which he said that obedience is to be desired, and that it leads to a good and peaceful life. Speaking to the English people after the civil war, he said that they should obey the crown, God, and their parents.

Beliefs must be classified as a powerful imaginary that orients people, not only according to traditional patterns coming from their own cultural identities, but also according to the interests linked to the management of political power.

Kohn prophetically said, modifying the first sentence of Karl Marx's Communist Manifesto, that "a ghost still haunts the world: the ghost of fundamentalism" (1992, p.63).

Millet (2000) also refers to fundamentalismo in regard to Hegels´s rejection of what he considers scientific fundamentalism, that is, all closed forms of thinking that claim to have definitive answers, but are not based exclusively on reason. In the end, perhaps this extends to all forms of social thought that claim to have answers to all the possible questions that can be posed by a thinking person.

Since then, Kohn’s premonition has become a warning and omen: it is increasingly common for men and women of the twenty-first century to manage their existential anxieties by meekly submitting to atavistic dictates that they have been taught to obey, and politicians take advantage of their need for spiritual shelter. This tendency fits in with Festinger’s idea of cognitive dissonance. That is, people’s cognitive insecurity makes them easy prey for political interests.

It then happens that this meek submission becomes horrifying when they are also shown the dagger of Abraham that they will have to wield as a test of their faith and as a sign of their devotion. They even perceive themselves as part of a just cause dedicated to the achievement of what is worthy and beneficial for the homeland, such as, racial supremacy, Sharia law, the evangelization of the natives and other ancestral goals. Today it is worse: political leaders chain the obedience of their followers to motivations that are not so patrimonial, such as the fortune of a transnational company and the maintenance of the prices of oil, diamonds, gold and copper.

Final Thoughts

The academic experiences of Milgram, Zimbardo, Moscovici, Skinner, and Festinger can help us understand the tragedies of Agamemnon and others, and perhaps give us alternatives. The proposals of these authors point to the environmental aspects of obedience, that is, those pressures that influence us culturally or socially to accept the domination of someone else. We have seen how twentieth-century jurisprudence, both national and international, has directed its attention to the legal limits of obedience seen as an obligation of State officials.  Mead, Schütz, and Sartre point to the internal resources we have to resist them.

I repeat Zimbardo’s (2007, Prologue, p. 6) observation (cited above): one of the main conclusions of the Stanford prison experiment is that the subtle but pervasive power of a multitude of situational variables can overcome a person’s the will to resist this influence.

The power wielded by the crowd can be paralyzing. But there are those who resist. There is a lot of debate about where the ability to act independently lies. Is it in the brain? Is it in hidden cultural resources?  Neurological experiments (Radder and Meynen, 2012, Libet, 1999 and others) have not yet shown clear evidence for the existence of conscious autonomy of decision-making processes. Interestingly, they found a "readiness potential," measured as an electrical impulse at the apex of the skull in electroencephalogram studies, that precedes the subject's awareness of his or her act. It is difficult to interpret these results philosophically, but they definitely do not contradict the idea of an impulsive "I" as proposed by Mead, Schültz, and Sartre.

Mead, Schültz, and Sartre mention the importance of reflection that occurs after the act, the accumulation of experience, and the elaboration of an intentional project. In many cases, it is a matter of individual preparation to face the situations that should be resisted. As in the case of the application of behavioral modification techniques, if the subject or patient knows about the dispositions of reward and punishment contingencies, and knows where they come from, he or she is in a position to make his or her own decisions. If Eric Fromm had picked up on Skinner's trick, he wouldn't have fallen into the ridiculousness of waving his hand in the air – as if he were just another pigeon in a behavioral experiment.

After the Second World War, especially after the Nuremberg Trials, there was a global reflection on repressive practices and the degree of responsibility that individuals have in this regard. It is still a timid debate; It appears infrequently in schools, universities and the media. The issue opens in the barracks only with occasional reiterations of the scant regulatory codes on the limits to due obedience. This discursive silence in the cantonments, among the police and in prisons prevents a valid and meaningful discussion about the right and obligation of a soldier, a security agent or a prisoner to break an order.

I have tried to explore certain types of obedience that can finally be classified into two categories: a) that which ends with submission and that can lead to vassalage and violence among the faithful, and b) that which results from a thoughtful decision to obey -or deny- the order received.

Although Hegel and Kierkegaard were Christians, I have not pointed to any particular dogma or ideology. Nevertheless, we may ask: What would have happened if Abraham had asked God why he wanted such a brutal proof of his devotion? Or if he had doubted the goodness of such a divine order?  Perhaps he could have been a renovator of the foundations of the Jewish, Christian and Muslim creeds.  This is not the place to imagine what changes he would have made to these traditions, but at least the devotee who has inherited these beliefs might have had the right to say "no" to the demands of dogmas that sometimes require blood. Modern conflicts, for example, between the Irish in the north and south, and the Israelis and the Palestinians would not have the same justification.

History, its legends and traditional texts cannot be modified, but modern laws can be reconstructed. In humanistic disciplines such as psychology, sociology, and philosophy, and in law schools, debates must be opened about the history of obedience in human culture. There must be renewed considerations about what are the conditions for provoking and controlling tyranny, and finally evaluations about what place awareness should occupy today. Part of individual and group autonomy is resisting unwanted influence from others. There are soldiers who die in modern "crusades," and terrorist insurgents who do not question the reasons for murdering others, taking revenge, and, in the process, blowing themselves up. On the other hand, the need to set limits in the upbringing of children and in the coexistence of citizens should be an obligatory part of ethics and civility.

What we have to ask is what kind of courage do we need today? Do we need that of the Kierkegaardian individual, isolated from his fellows, who blindly obeys as Abraham did? We must pay attention to other models: Nelson Mandela said "no" to Apartheid and was even able to negotiate a relationship of non-submission with his own jailer in South Africa. In captivity, he cultivated an ethic of obedience to his own conscience.

 

BIBLIOGRAPHY

 

Antigone full text.pdf. (n.d.). Google Docs. https://drive.google.com/file/d/0B4WAgAXpP-vJX0tVejJ0Uml1cTA/view?resourcekey=0-VKLoNyVfLKY1kIyrZTaQrg

Asch, S. E. (1956). Studies of independence and conformity: I. A minority of one against a unanimous majority. Psychological Monographs: General and Applied, 70, 9, 1–70. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0093718

 Balcazar, F.E., Keys, C.B, and Julie A. Vryhof, J.A. (2019). Empowerment.  In L. A. Jason; O. Glantsman; J. F. O'Brien; & K. N. Ramian (Editors). Introduction to community psychology. Rebus Community.   https://press.rebus.community/introductiontocommunitypsychology/chapter/empowerment/

Burger, J. M. (2009, Januaryx). Replicating Milgram. Would people still obey today? American Psychologist. 64, 1, 1–11. https://pdfs.semanticscholar.org/b5d3/43985f72c0d8b45e4013c6e381cc8707793b.pdf?_ga=2.207930578.1382187499.1563372591-290466741.1563372591

Cavada,  J. P. (April, 2019). Obediencia debida de órdenes ilícitas.  (Due obedience of illicit orders).  Library of the National Congress of Chile. Supplement 119837. https://www.bcn.cl/obtienearchivo?id=repositorio/10221/27106/2/Obediencia_debida._Legislacion_nacional__internacional_y_extranjera.pdf

Conorman and Dualan Attorneys at Law (2022, March 16). Can you recognize an unlawful order?  Military Justice Center. https://www.militaryjusticecenter.com/blog/2022/03/can-you-recognize-an-unlawful-order/

Cronick, K. (2018). The hero's grip. (El agarre del héroe). SaberUCV. ttp://saber.ucv.ve/bitstream/123456789/17950/1/completo%20heroe.pdf

Cronick, K. (2024), La empatía: una capacidad en los seres vivos. (Empathy: a capacity that living beings have). L. Mora-Salas (Coord.). Testimonios psicosociales. Cuaderno de Investigación N° 1 - Área Psicología Social. Doctorado en Psicología. CDCH/UCV (In evaluation).

EcuRed (n.d.). Nuremberg Trials. (Juicios de Núremberg).  https://www.ecured.cu/Juicios_de_N%C3%BAremberg

Euripides (409 BC / n.d.) Iphigenia in Aulis. Skidmore College. https://classics.domains.skidmore.edu/lit-campus-only/primary/translations/Euripides%20Iph%20Aul.pdf

Euripides (near 414 /2001). Iphigenia in Tauris. Blackmask. http://public-library.uk/ebooks/49/96.pdf

Festinger, L (1968).  A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance. Stanford University Press) https://archive.org/details/FestingerLeonATheoryOfCognitiveDissonance1968StanfordUniversityPress

Hegel, F. (1807/1987). Fenomenología del espíritu. (Phenomenology of the Spirit). Mexico: Fondo de Cultura Económica.

Hobbes, T. (1651/n.d.). Leviathan. Freeditorial.  https://freeditorial.com/es/books/leviatan/related-books

Kierkegaard, S. (1849/1954). Fear and trembling and sickness unto death. Trans. Walter Lowrie. New York: Doubleday.

Kohn, C. (1992, December). “¿Es posible definir el Fundamentalismo como una ideología política?”, (Is it possible to define fundamentalism as a political ideology?)   Extramuros  (Journal of  the Humanities and Education Faculty of  the Central University of Venezuela). 6, 63-78.

la Boétie, E. (1572/2015). Discurso sobre la servidumbre voluntaria (Discourse on voluntary servitude).  Cyngular Asesoría

Libet, B. (1999). Do we have free will? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6, 47–57.

Mead, G. H. (1913/1972). Spirit, Person and Society. (Espíritu, Persona y Sociedad). Buenos Aires: Paidós

Milgram, S. (1963) Behavioral study of obedience. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology. 67, 4, 371-378. https://www.psy.miami.edu/_assets/pdf/rpo-articles/milgram-1963.pdf

Milgram Stanley (2005). Los peligros de la obediencia. (The dangers of obedience). POLIS, Revista Latinoamericana. 4, 11. ISSN: 0717-6554. https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=30541124

Millet, J.M. (2000). Hegel y el fundamentalismo moderno. Diálogos 75, pp. 7-35.  https://core.ac.uk/download/pdf/71020513.pdf

Moscovici, S. (1996).  Psicología de las minorías activas. (The psychology of active minorities.). Barcelona: Morata

Psyciencia (2015, February 17). El día que Skinner condicionó a Erich Fromm. (The day Skinner conditioned Erich Fromm). https://www.psyciencia.com/el-dia-que-skinner-condiciono-a-erich-fromm/

Radder, H. & Meynen, G. (October 7, 2012). Does the brain "initiate" freely willed processes? A philosophy of science critique of Libet-type experiments and their interpretation. Theory & Psychology, 23(1), 3-21. http://tap.sagepub.com/content/early/2012/10/15/0959354312460926

Rivero V., R. (April, 2016). Memory: Due Obedience of Unlawful Orders in Chilean and Spanish Criminal Law and Military Criminal Law. (Memoria: La Obediencia Debida de Órdenes Ilícitas en el Derecho Penal y Derecho Penal Militar Chileno y Español.). Pontificia Universidad Católica de Valparaíso, Faculty of Law, School of Law. http://bcn.cl/29ido.

Sartre, J.P. (1943/1989) El ser y la nada. (Being and Nothingness).  Madrid: Alianza.

Schütz, A. (1932/1993). La construcción significativa del mundo social. (The phenomenology of the social world).  Barcelona: Paidós.

Skinner, B.F. (1985) A Matter of Consequences. New York: New York University Press

Solzhenitsyn, A. (1962/2008). A Day in the Life of Ivan Denisovich. (Un día en la vida de Iván Denísovich).  Barcelona: Tusquets Editores S.A.

Zimbardo, P. G. (2007).  El efecto Lucifer. El porqué de la maldad. (The Lucifer effect. The reason for the evil.). Barcelona: Paidos. https://upanacollipsicopatolcrim19622013.files.wordpress.com/2013/11/zimbardo-philip-el-efecto-lucifer.pdf

Zimbardo, P. G. (2009). Stanford Prison Experiment. Official Website http://www.prisonexp.org/.

 

 

 

 

 

 



[1] Old Testament. Genesis. Chapter 22, verses 1-12.

[2] The severity of the Old Testament was radically changed in the New Testament. It is to be remembered that the New Testament was transcribed in historical times while the Old Testament represents millennia of oral history. Jesus is quoted as saying: “Thou shalt love the Lord thy God with all thy heart, and with all thy soul, and with all thy mind. This is the first and great commandment. And the second is like unto it, Thou shalt love thy neighbor as thyself. On these two commandments hang all the law and the prophets”. (New Testament. Matthew. Chapter 22. Verses 36-40. King James Version)

[3] Both these stories may represent historical allegories about the end of human sacrifice. To support this idea, we can refer to another of Euripides' plays, Iphigenia in Tauris (2001), in which she receives divine pardon and survives.

[4] The Old Testament, Genesis 22

[5] This division of the consciousness began with Hegel’s separation of “being” into an “I” and the “Other”. He also elaborated this division with other classifications, some of which I mention in this article. My interpretation of The Phenomenology of the Spirit owes more to its later influence in psychoanalysis and existentialism, and less to the tradition that led to Marx. Later Freud divided consciousness into Ego, Superego, and Id, referring to the contrast between self-awareness, morality, and desire. Other authors such as Mead, Schütz and Sartre later developed their own interpretations of the subdivisions of the aware being.

[6] In Hegel the “for-itself  (für sich). Is a reflective, self-comprehending, form of consciousness.

[7] In Hegle the “in-itself” (an sich) is a hypothetical, unreflective form of consciousness. It is a kind of potentiality with no reference to other things. 

[8] For this reason, tyrants often attempt to eliminate or reduce massive educational projects.

 
Locations of visitors to this page